Key insights from
After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory
By
Alasdair MacIntyre
|
|
|
What you’ll learn
“Justice,” “goodness,”
“courage”: Words like these clamor through modern speech wearing the guise
of moral weight. They might sound pretty to listening ears, but their
beauty is often highly illusory. The words typically associated with moral
action are barren, each echoing through modern-day discourse as if it has a
purpose that, in reality, it no longer holds. What one person views as
morally justified another views as ethically questionable, each appealing
to entirely different, indissoluble realms of moral truth. Renowned
philosopher Alasdair MacIntyre crafts a brilliant, unnerving account of
humanity’s failure to speak meaningfully in the context of morality,
tracking the evolution of that highly contentious word virtue across
centuries of philosophy—from the pillars of Athens to the experiments of
the Enlightenment.
Read
on for key insights from After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory.
|
|
Sponsored
by Morning Brew
Get Smarter in 5
Minutes
There's a reason over 3 million people
start their day with Morning Brew — the daily email that delivers the
latest news from Wall Street to Silicon Valley. Business news doesn't have
to be dry and dense...make your mornings more enjoyable, for free.
Check it out
|
|
1. Dialogues about
morality have devolved into idle monologues—we’re too far from Athens to
know what virtue even is.
What determines an
individual’s right to life, or the context of a “just war?” Is human
happiness an attainable goal or simply an idle reverie? How might true
equality exist in society without infringing upon the equity of others? The
trembling ground of modern discourse indicates that at some point along the
steep line of history, words pertaining to virtue came loose from their
original definitions—the traditional, invariable basis underlying all words
pertaining to morality is broken. Ancient Athens is far off our radar, but
it's misused lingo dangerously persists (and it’s all Greek to our modern
ears).
Nowadays, common
understanding concerning questions of morality is difficult to envision,
and entreaties on both sides of an issue appear equally sound and ethically
viable. For this reason, there doesn’t appear to be what MacIntyre terms a
“rational,” or a thoughtful and absolute way to resolve conflict. Differing
spheres of argumentation stretch into infinitum as self-sustaining circles,
never to touch or intersect with competing explanations or moral theories.
Mutual understanding is as foreign in modern culture as the verbiage of
“virtue”—a word that fell from its original roots in Aristotelian thought,
through the grinder of the Enlightenment, only to tumble as incoherent
shards into the lap of a distraught and confused modernity.
One of the most notable
attributes of the tenuous speech surrounding matters of virtue and morality
is its “conceptual incommensurability.” In the presence of competing
theories on the same issue, neither side is able to win or triumph over its
opponent with an explanation that makes sense on both sides of the aisle.
One arguer’s line of thinking is perfectly self-sustained in the context of
its initial assumption, so how she arrives at her conclusion appears
perfectly valid. But when one side of an argument meets its match, it grows
apparent that both lines of reasoning are only justified in the context of
their original proposition—the arguments can’t appeal to an outer standard
of morality; rather, they both posit a distinct “normative or evaluative
concept” that prohibits their interaction with ideological competitors.
Both explanations are irreconcilable in the presence of one another,
leading to the sense that seemingly sound, morally justifiable arguments
are nothing more than veneers of personal opinion.
As MacIntyre argues, in
order to glimpse our situation for what it is, we must remove ourselves
from our highly particular, historical moment in time. As difficult as it
may be, if we wish to broach the true, inalterable essence of virtue and
morality, we must put ourselves into the shoes of some very ancient and
some other not-so-distant ancestors. Peeling back history to uncover the
content of morality, we should slip on the dusty sandals of an Athenian and
become a student of the able Aristotle.
|
|
2. Aristotle
taught that humanity has a “telos,” or a communal purpose paved by virtue.
The accounts of seafaring
military men and lovely, dutiful maidens fill the heroic tradition,
spotting the cultural conscience of hearers and readers alike, including those
lucky enough to be among Homer’s first listeners. In the verbose poet’s Iliad, believed to
have been compiled in the 7th century, virtue is called “areté,” and it denotes
proficiency in any kind of skill or action. According to classics scholars,
the virtues of the heroic individual were tethered to her culturally
prescribed identity and how she acted within that particular position—they
were inherently communal and obligatory. Heroic characters thought little
of questioning this “dikê,”
translated by Hugh Lloyd Jones as “the order of the universe,” acting
within their communities with the utmost compliance.
This seemingly spotless
portrait underwent various changes into 5th century Athens, which
pulled apart the strings of virtue to puzzle over the true content of “dikaiosunê” or
“justice.” Despite prevailing disagreement over the content of the virtues
even then, Athenian thinkers were adamant about one thing—whatever virtues
are, their proper place is the “polis,”
the community within which both people and actions receive meaning and
value.
Virtue cycled through
various permutations until it fell at the feet of Aristotle, the brilliant
Athenian philosopher who gave classical philosophy a succinct explanation
of the virtues in his Nicomachean
Ethics. From this point on, virtue was posited as a course of
action upon which a person may reach her “telos,” or the ultimate fulfillment of
one’s humanity within specific communities or relationships. Virtue was
guided by principles that rose above simple reality, and its power served
everyone it touched.
When a person acts
according to her sense of virtue, she acts “kata ton orthon logon,” or “according to
right reason,” using her judgement to decipher the best course between two
vices, or extremes. As opposed to the heroic individual, the Athenian isn’t
simply prescribed a course of action but must set out upon a route for
herself according to her own informed reason and quest toward virtue. “Phronêsis,” or
well-executed judgement, is one virtue that unlocks the plethora of virtues
we typically think of when pondering what it means to be a good person.
Over time, a person’s initially wild or unrestrained tendencies come under
the jurisdiction of judgement and contribute to a virtuous identity that
may effectively partake in the polis.
Though the practice of the
virtues both emulates and leads to the ultimate purpose of human life
(which Aristotle said existed in the joy of thinking), it does so
independently of that ultimate purpose. Virtue is practiced for the sake of
the virtuous and the benefit of the polis.
When an individual bends her desires to her reason and to what she knows
the telos of
a human is, she acts virtuously and gains fulfillment—a satisfactory
byproduct of a life lived thoughtfully.
Though Aristotle’s
teachings remain present in the decisive atmosphere of modern thought, his
recognition of an overarching telos
for humankind is largely absent. Moreover, his cumulative conception of
virtue as reasonable action has collapsed as well, crumbling in a seismic
shift that fractured the world with apparent insight: the Enlightenment
threw Aristotle’s conclusions into ideological confusion, and the world’s
been reeling ever since.
|
|
3. The
Enlightenment shattered a unifying telos into shards of disillusionment.
In an era of minds
awakening to the bright light of scientific possibility, humanity’s telos fell into the
shadows. As Newton calculated the laws of cosmic gravity, the role of the
microscopic human grew unclear. Scientists and philosophers alike sought to
put their abilities and the possibilities of the material world to the
test, unfettered by past connotations of meaning and humanity at large.
Primarily led by Northern European intellectuals and cultural figureheads
in the 17th and 18th centuries, many thinkers of the Enlightenment sought
to identify an explainable reason for moral action in the absence of the
seemingly limiting worlds of religion and tradition—a quest that resulted
in philosophical shortcomings that pervade cultural thought today.
Every philosopher’s
insights built upon his predecessors’ during this highly impactful period
in philosophical and cultural thought. Amidst the shortcomings of the
philosophers Denis Diderot and David Hume to locate the source of ethical
action in an individual’s desire to act properly, Immanuel Kant looked for
a way to think of morality as an actionable response to human reason. For
him, this sense of reason transcends fleeting cultural values into that of
“universalizability.” This concept holds that an action is only moral if it
is practicable by any person at any point in history—a pretty difficult
theory to prove in the wake of the unpredictable variety of human life.
Inspired by these
intellectual giants’ glaring oversights, Søren Kierkegaard laid out his own
explanation for moral conduct in his work Enten-Eller (Either/Or). Therein, he declines Diderot,
Hume, and Kant’s descriptions of moral conduct as reliant upon either
desire or reason. Instead, Kierkegaard concludes that the decision to live
ethically is simply a matter of preference, in which the individual chooses
whether or not to recognize the place of right and wrong in the world. If a
person accepts that the “good” truly exists, than she lives accordingly,
but this way of living is optional—a proposition that chocks morality to
matters of personal opinion and lifestyle. Kierkegaard’s existential
worries are symptomatic of the Enlightenment period, and they obliterate
Aristotle’s assumptions that virtue and true human value exist.
In light of each
philosopher’s inability to justify human morality, the culture of the
Enlightenment was left with nothing to fall back on. Without Aristotle’s
firm acknowledgement of a human telos,
and amidst the abandonment of Protestant and Catholic beliefs, human beings
also abandoned their collective assumption that human purpose and virtue
are idyllic goals to be sought. Where seekers thought they uncovered moral,
individual enlightenment, they actually wandered upon epistemic
disillusionment. In this wasteland, they misread their fall as a personal
freedom, ushering in the presently pervasive age of the “individual.”
|
|
4. “Emotivism”
dominates modernity’s sense of virtue, and establishes the “individual” as
the sole moral compass.
Society has fallen far from
Aristotle’s idyllic conception of moral virtue, through the
discombobulating ranks of Enlightenment theories and into the ideology of
“emotivism.” This theory pulses through contemporary thought and consists
of the pervasive belief that all moral meaning is ambiguous, propelled by a
particular person’s self-justifiable, individual beliefs. According to the
work of C. L. Stevenson, a 20th century philosopher and advocate for emotivism,
a statement that refers to something as “good” is simply a more polished
and persuasive way of saying, “I like this.” There’s nothing beyond the
previously morally weighty term of “good.” Virtue and the “self” are
vacant, outdated concepts.
The contemporary thinking
of emotivism can be sourced to G. E. Moore’s highly influential work Principia Ethica,
which took the intellectual world by storm in the 19th century. Moore
appealed to a concept called “intuitionism” to explain an individual’s
morality as a personal matter. MacIntyre asserts that modern-day emotivism
“rests upon a claim that every attempt, whether past or present, to provide
a rational justification for an objective morality has in fact failed,”
leading practitioners to the assumption that the most significant aspects
of discourse pertaining to moral action are how it appeals to the
individual and how it impacts the listener. Within this understanding,
words of morality function as ideological weaponry, swaying individual
minds toward particular, impassioned opinions.
In an age in which communal
ties to a specific identity or cultural structure are largely severed,
words that posit a merely useful reality of virtue are especially
persuasive tools. MacIntyre identifies three central “characters” of the
contemporary era who each encapsulate, enact, and promote a particular
perception of cultural virtue. The characters of the “Rich Aesthete,” the
“Manager,” and the “Therapist” idealize the aims of emotivism that cloak
selfish coercion in the disguise of moral weight. Each of these characters
employs the individual person to achieve a particular goal, using their
impassioned discourse to ignite a similar sensation in hearers. In this
way, they maintain their cultural appeal and occupy a deceptive throne of
control over others.
The evolution of the
individual’s notion of the “self” and the discourse of virtue are
intertwined, producing today’s culture of “modern liberalism.” This
liberalism is less associated with political parties than it is with
cultural worldview—the disintegration of collectivity and the relegation of
the individual person to an alienated function are the outcomes of a
culture that’s forgotten the content of morality. Culture is stranded in
the sea of itself—without an all-encompassing, communal sense of moral
worth and the value of virtue, human beings captain their ships alone,
struggling to steer themselves toward a moral landing place they no longer
believe in.
|
|
5. The answer to
our moral mayhem is the ancient polis—we need common relational bonds to
believe in virtue again.
What do we do in the midst
of a fractious environment? Where do we turn when the traditionally
fulfilling virtues are nothing more than words falling into societal
silence? In the wake of the inadequacies of contemporary culture to
identify human value and moral meaning, people must return to the Athenian
lifestyle emulated in the thinking of Aristotle. Just as Aristotle and
other ancient Greek thinkers upheld the polis
as the sphere in which both the individual and moral virtue received
validation, contemporary people must collaborate to partake in small groups
of people or as MacIntyre writes, “local forms of community.” Whatever this
looks like from person to person, these small segments of society should
operate holistically and seek to practice true virtue for virtue’s sake and
for the benefit of others and one’s own individual realization.
MacIntyre describes a
cautionary similarity between contemporary culture and the culture of the
dwindling Roman Empire. Before Roman culture succumbed to the Dark Ages,
its people started to look away from the Empire as their source of meaning
and provider of morality. As such, they developed alternate spaces in which
they could live their lives apart from the Empire, allowing for their
identities, customs, and beliefs to persevere. In these separate spheres,
people practiced virtuous living and enabled their lifestyles to persist
despite the oncoming Dark Ages. While the situation of the modern person
isn’t nearly as grim as that of the disillusioned Roman’s, a lesson may be
learned: To ensure the survival of concepts as scarce and sacred as virtue,
morality, and what truly matters to the life of a human being, people must
find or create their own groups—individual bodies of people striving to
live humane and cooperative lifestyles.
These kinds of groups can
be simple, but their function serves a great purpose—the preservation of a
satisfied life and the continuance of moral action. Humanity does indeed
have a telos,
and the realization of such is intertwined with the lives of others—being
“truthful,” “courageous,” or “patient” means nothing without the active
participation of many people. According to Aristotle, all of life is a
stretching toward “eudaimonia,”
or simply “the state of being well and doing well in being well.” Without
true moral living, this reality is illusory and humanity grows aimless and
numb. If we want to find areté,
we must discover it together, in the presence of others. Morality is a path
best traveled in company, and its destination is timelessly fulfilling,
both for the ancient Athenian and for the modern American, too.
|
|
No comments:
Post a Comment